Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Canterbury Law Review |
Last Updated: 8 January 2013
WORKPLACE APPEARANCE STANDARDS: UNDRESSING THE
LAW
NATASHA CALDWELL*
I. INTRODUCTION
If a lady rebels against wearing high-heeled shoes, she should
take care to do so in a very smart hat.
(George Bernard Shaw, 1928)
As dress and appearance are forms of social language, serving to communicate
'a panoply of social messages',1 it is unsurprising many employers
seek to impose restrictions on the appearance of their employees in the
workplace. Although the
imposition of gendered appearance standards in the
workforce may appear unobjectionable to many, such requirements not only have
problematic normative underpinnings but also present significant difficulties
for individuals whose gendered identities do not conform
with societal
norms.
Significantly, the issue as to whether a gender based appearance
requirement can contravene New Zealand's human rights legislation
has been left
open by the New Zealand Employment Court, and judicial examination of this
pertinent issue has been sparse in this
jurisdiction. However, a significant
corpus of law regarding the legality of sex-differentiated employment dress
codes has developed
under the comparable legislative frameworks of America and
England. In both jurisdictions the relevant legislation prohibits unlawful
discrimination in employment, with reference to the less favourable treatment of
employees on the grounds of 'sex', and the definitions
of unlawful
discrimination in both jurisdictions thus bear a striking similarity to that
found in the provisions of New Zealand's
domestic human rights
legislation.
This article therefore aims both to analyse the legal reasoning
employed by the overseas courts in their determination of the legality
of gender
based dress codes and to evaluate the policy concerns that have been relied upon
to reject recognition of such discrimination
claims. This analysis is undertaken
with a view to ascertaining the appropriate judicial path that the New Zealand
courts should
take in determining the legality of gendered appearance standards
under New Zealand's human rights framework. A comparative analysis
of the
international jurisprudence has not been previously undertaken in academic
literature; and the question of how the New Zealand
courts would determine the
legality of appearance standards under current legislation has not been
subjected to previous examination.
This article therefore seeks to uncover the
impact that the international jurisprudence could have in New Zealand's
legislative setting
and, finally, to propose a way forward.
II. PRELIMINARY ISSUES
'Sex' and 'Gender'
In order to examine the significant role that dress and appearance can play
in the construction of one's gendered identity, it is
necessary to examine the
theoretical exposition that has developed in regards to the distinctions to be
drawn between the categories
of 'sex' and 'gender'. The term 'sex' is used to
refer to the irreducible biological classification that is made between the
sexed
male and female body, pursuant to the medical procedure of chromosomal
typing or the ascertainment of an infant's genitalia at the
time of
birth.2 An individual's classification into the sexed category of
male or female thus amounts to no more than a simple biological delineation.
In
contrast, the conception of 'gender' encapsulates the more elusive concept of
the masculine or feminine characteristics that identify
an individual as male or
female.3 The two concepts are quite distinct.
Essentialist
ideology has historically prescribed that an individual's gendered identity is
inherently linked to his or her biological
sex. Accordingly, under the
essentialist theoretical framework, the behaviours and characteristics
associated with the concepts of
masculinity and femininity are regarded as
intrinsically entwined with the sexed body.4 This rigid binaristic
division leaves no room for any acceptance of the possibility of gender fluidity
occurring within its confines.
However, a conflicting proposition which emerges
from post-modernist thought is the assertion that gender is in fact inherently
fluid.
In contrast to the essentialist notion that an individual's gendered
identity is biologically predicated upon the sexed body, post-modern
scholarship
proposes that gender can be viewed as a 'free floating artifice' that remains
unlinked to an individual's biological
sex.5 The perceived intrinsic
nature of gender identity is argued to be created through a series of repeated
acts that include 'bodily
gestures, movements and the stylisation of the body',
rather than through biological dictates.6 Gender is accordingly
viewed as essentially performative.
In light of the fundamental role that the
'stylisation of the body' holds in the construction of gender identity, it is no
surprise
that dress, grooming, and appearance, are generally seen to be the most
important indicator of gender difference in daily social
interactions.7 The use of gender based dress and appearance standards
in the workplace is thereby an effective tool by which gender differences
can be
accentuated.8 However, while gendered dress requirements may appear
to be superficially benign, such standards do have harmful normative
implications.
It is accordingly instructive to examine the fundamental policy
concerns that arise with the imposition of such standards in the
workplace.
Female Equality
A fundamental aim of sex discrimination law is to ensure that women are
assured of access to the same rights and freedoms as are granted
to men.9
However, any judicial approach that allows employers the ability to impose
standards of grooming or dress that perpetuate dominant
gender norms will
inevitably hinder the achievement of this objective. In order to understand the
feminist concerns regarding the
imposition of gendered dress codes in the
workplace, it is necessary to explore briefly both the normative underpinnings
of dominant
gender ideologies, and the societal structure within which they are
created.
The prevailing gender ideologies that pervade Western society are
premised upon the purported contrast between male and female behavioural
characteristics. Under dominant cultural dictates, true masculinity is equated
with the traits of aggressiveness and power, while
the ideal characteristics of
femininity are believed to include the traits of submissiveness and
servility.10 Such gender norms are thus framed within a patriarchal
structural framework predicated upon a societal belief in masculine dominance
and superiority.11 A logical corollary of this cultural framework,
which reinforces the purported inferiority of females, is the subsequent
societal
emphasis placed on the importance of a female's aesthetic appearance.
Under patriarchal ideology the significance of a female's appearance
gains
paramountcy, as it is considered vital that women are able to both please and
remain attractive to men.12 Female dress is a powerful tool by which
such oppressive norms can be propagated. Orthodox items of female attire, such
as high heeled
shoes and skirts, communicate the demeaning messages of female
weakness, dependency, and availability for sexual or emotional
service.13 Such social messages are inherently degrading for all
women.
Accordingly, the reproduction of dominant gender appearance norms in the
employment arena is particularly problematic. Dress and grooming
standards that
mandate conformity with stereotypical forms of feminine appearance reinforce
derogatory ideals which can effectively
inhibit female progression in the
workforce. Skill, competence, and work ethic should always hold greater priority
in the workplace
than the ability of a female employee to portray a feminine
appearance.14 However, any judicial acceptance of workplace
appearance standards that encompass traditional notions of femininity reinforces
the
view that a female employee's ability to conform to aesthetic feminine
ideals can legitimately amount to an important and relevant
employment
consideration. Such a prospect has far-reaching implications, and is hardly
conducive towards ensuring attainment of the
goal of achieving female equality
in the workforce.
It is apparent that any emphasis placed upon the appearance
of females in the workplace will hinder intellectual and job development
in a
number of ways. The American Psychological Association has established, for
instance, that concerns held by females about their
appearance reduces the
availability of their cognitive resources required to process actions and
thoughts.15 Mandating compliance with a traditionally feminine
appearance in the workplace has also been found to interfere with the respect
accorded
to the professional capabilities of female employees.16 Such
consequences are manifestly undesirable.
Transgender Equality
Not only do gendered based dress codes present obstacles to the goal of attaining female equality in the workforce, they also create significant employment barriers for transgendered individuals. The term 'transgender' is used to refer to a 'person whose identity does not conform unambiguously to conventional notions of male or female gender, but combines or moves between these'.17 Thus, a transgendered individual will often outwardly present a gender identity that may not reconcile with his or her biological sex. As emphasised by the Human Rights Commission, all transgendered people should, by virtue of their common humanity, be entitled to the protection and promotion of their human rights.18 However, an employment dress policy that requires a connection between gendered presentation and biological sex will often carry significant psychological implications for transgendered people, and may create unassailable barriers towards their entry and assimilation in the workforce.19 The imposition of gender based appearance requirements will thus both marginalise and subordinate transgendered individuals. Such an outcome cannot be seen to accord with the ideals of social justice underpinning anti-discrimination legislation.
III. NEW ZEALAND JURISPRUDENCE
The Human Rights Act 1993
The Human Rights Act 199320 was enacted with the goal of ensuring the effective protection of human rights in New Zealand, and of honouring New Zealand's commitment to international human rights covenants.21 A fundamental tenet that permeates such international instruments is the principle that all individuals should be granted the right to equality of opportunity and treatment in employment;22 and s 22 of the Human Rights Act reflects the importance of this right through its explicit proscription of unlawful discrimination in employment on any of the prohibited grounds.23 This prohibition of unlawful discrimination in employment is also reflected in s 104 of the Employment Relations Act 2000,24 contravention of which can give rise to a personal grievance claim.25 The particular ground of discrimination that is the subject of discussion in this article is that of 'sex, including pregnancy and childbirth' under s 21(1)(a) of the Human Rights Act.26 Although this is a prohibited ground of particularly longstanding, the potential breadth of the parameters of the term 'sex' remains largely untested.27 In light of the uncertainty surrounding the possible scope of s 21(1)(a) of the Act, the issue as to whether the prohibition of unlawful discrimination on the grounds of 'sex' could extend to the prohibition of gender based dress codes is one of some significance.
Williams v Kimberlys Fashions Ltd
The potential utility of New Zealand's human rights legislation in
prohibiting gendered appearance standards remains an unresolved
issue, following
the decision of the Employment Court in Williams v Kimberleys Fashions
Ltd.28 In Williams, the Court was presented with
the opportunity of exploring the issue of whether the defendant's requirement
that the complainant (a
female sales assistant in its retail fashion store),
wear facial make-up was in contravention of New Zealand's human rights
legislation.
The complainant objected to the wearing of make-up, on the grounds
that cosmetic foundation reacted badly with her skin, and she
believed that
because 'it was no longer the 1950s' women should be able to choose whether or
not to wear make-up at work.29 While it was accepted by the Court
that the defendant's requirement had had a significant effect on the
complainant's psychological
well-being, by creating feelings of despondency over
her appearance, and exacerbating symptoms of depression,30 the Court,
through opting to resolve the issue on a contractual basis, successfully evaded
undertaking any substantive analysis of
the wider discrimination issues that the
compulsory make-up requirement could entail.
Holding that there was neither a
contractual condition necessitating the use of facial make-up for the
complainant, nor any evidence
that attempts to introduce the requirement as part
of the employer's house rules were properly communicated to the complainant, the
Court concluded that the respondent had no contractual entitlement to insist
upon compliance with this appearance standard. Accordingly,
the respondent's
insistence on the complainant's use of facial make-up, despite knowledge of the
complainant's aversion to cosmetics,
was held to amount to a breach of its duty
to 'not act in a manner calculated to destroy or seriously damage the employment
relationship'.31 This breach formed one of the 'major factors'32
that contributed to the success of the complainant's alternative claim of
constructive dismissal.
The resolution of this issue on contractual grounds
allowed the Court to avoid examination of the question as to whether a
contractual
condition necessitating the use of facial make-up for female
employees could fall foul of New Zealand's human rights legislation.
The
possibility of a full substantive analysis of the matter was in fact given short
shrift. Simply acknowledging that the issue
was 'fraught with difficulties' the
Court declared that any substantive engagement with the matter was better left
for 'argument
on another occasion';33 and thus the key issue, which
is of considerable importance for human rights law in New Zealand, was very
briefly dispensed with
and remains unresolved.
Although the Employment Court
in Williams declined to provide any determinative guidance on the
legality of the compulsory facial make-up requirement, a few brief obiter
observations
made by the Court do shed some light on the current judicial
attitude towards the imposition of gender based grooming requirements
in the
workplace. Both the Court's observation that 'there may well be workplaces where
the nature of the work requires facial make-up,
such as a women's cosmetic
retail shop', and its reasoning that it was 'not beyond argument' that an
employer in a woman's clothing
boutique could require its staff to wear facial
make-up if it was a 'mutual contractual requirement',34 indicated a
judicial belief in the assumed innocuous nature of this grooming requirement.
This judicial attitude is of some concern.
Considerable legal and policy issues
surround the imposition of gender based appearance requirements, and the Court's
cursory treatment
of these issues was therefore unfortunate. The reluctance to
examine the issues in greater depth was not, however, altogether surprising.
Any
judicial determination of the legality of gender based appearance standards
would require the courts to explore the intricacies
of sex and gender identity,
and to grapple with significant arguments of policy. The task does not lend
itself to easy resolution.
We are thus drawn to question how the New Zealand
courts should attempt to confront this crucial matter. And in order to ascertain
the appropriate judicial path that should be taken, it is instructive to examine
and evaluate the legal principles that have arisen
from the international
jurisprudence surrounding the legality of the imposition of gender based
appearance standards in the workforce.
IV. AMERICAN JURISPRUDENCE
Title VII Civil Rights Act 1964
A very substantial body of jurisprudence regarding the legality of
sex-differentiated dress codes has developed under America's federal
anti-discrimination legislation, Title VII Civil Rights Act 1964. This
legislation provides that it shall be an unlawful employment practice for an
employer to discriminate against any individual
with respect to his or her terms
or conditions of employment because of his or her 'sex'.35 While the
concept of discrimination is not defined by the legislation, it has been
judicially established that direct discrimination
will be established under the
Act when an employer treats some employees 'less favourably' than others
pursuant to a prohibited ground
of discrimination.36 Accordingly,
discrimination under Title VII would be found to have occurred where an
employee receives less favourable terms or conditions of employment, because of
his or her
sex. It becomes immediately apparent that this concept of direct
discrimination is analogous to the prohibition under the Human Rights Act
1993 of 'less favourable' terms or conditions of employment by reason of sex
pursuant to s 22(1)(b).37
While the concept of indirect
discrimination is also prohibited under Title VII,38 an
appearance standard sex discrimination claim inevitably falls within the scope
of a direct discrimination claim. A gender based
appearance standard, such as a
requirement to wear make-up, does not apply equally to all male and female
employees, and is thus
not a term or condition that is neutral on its
face.39 The American cases therefore concern direct discrimination
alone.
Very significantly, the legislative prohibition of discrimination on
the grounds of 'sex' under Title VII has been accorded a liberal
interpretation by the United States Supreme Court, pursuant to its proscription
of sex stereotyping in
the seminal decision of Price Waterhouse v
Hopkins.40 Here, the female claimant, employed as a senior
manager within the employer's accounting firm, was denied a promotion to
partnership
level, despite having attained consistent recognition for her
professional capabilities. The coup de grace of her subsequent sex
discrimination claim, brought under Title VII, was the advice given by an
employing partner to the claimant to 'walk more femininely, talk more
femininely, dress more femininely,
wear make-up, have [her] hair styled and wear
jewellery'.41
Justice Brennan, delivering the plurality judgment,
held that the employer's refusal to promote the claimant — an employment
decision that was motivated by sex stereotyping amounting to an 'impermissibly
cabined view of the proper behaviour of women' —
contravened the
legislative protection provided by Title VII.42 Hereby,
it was established that employment decisions driven by stereotyped gendered
ideals could amount to employment discrimination
that occurred because of 'sex',
and the Supreme Court's acknowledgement that requiring an employee to conform to
stereotypes associated
with his or her sex would contravene Title VII was
a groundbreaking step in the progression of America's sex discrimination
law.43 Explicitly recognising the dangers of propagating gendered
ideals in the workplace, the plurality judges' landmark pronouncement
that
'gender must be irrelevant to employment decisions',44 and their
emphatic affirmation that 'Congress intended to strike at the entire spectrum of
disparate treatment of men and women deriving
from sex
stereotypes',45 revealed an unmistakable willingness to look beyond
the rigid dichotomies of biological sex so as to recognise the harms perpetuated
through employer adherence to the orthodox ideals of masculinity and
femininity.
Jespersen v Harrah's Operating Company
The United States Supreme Court has not yet been presented with the opportunity to provide definitive guidance on the appropriate judicial approach to be taken towards the specific dress code issue, but the recent decision of Jespersen v Harrah's Operating Company,46 heard en banc by the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, is now widely accepted as having provided authoritative framework by which dress code discrimination claims are to be decided in the United States.47 This appellate decision accordingly provides an excellent platform from which the prevailing American judicial approach towards the imposition of gender based dress codes in the workplace can be explored.
In order to examine the legal analysis employed by the Ninth Circuit in
Jespersen, it is necessary first to traverse the factual background. The
impetus behind this sex discrimination claim was the complainant's dismissal
from employment as a bartender following her non-compliance with the employer's
requirement that female bartenders wear full facial
make-up during their hours
of work. This make-up stipulation, encompassed within the employer's wider
'Personal Best' dress policy,
had been introduced under the guise of a wider
'Beverage Department Image Transformation' scheme.48 Although the
dress policy mandated use of the same unisex uniform for male and female
bartenders alike, the grooming standards under
the policy differed significantly
for both sexes. In contrast to the requirements that males had to wear their
hair above collar
length, and have clean hands with neatly trimmed nails, the
hair of female bartenders was to be presented in a style that was 'teased
or
curled', while finger-nails were to be adorned with nail-polish.49
The make-up requirement included within the policy stipulated that face powder,
blush, mascara and lip colour was to be worn in 'complementary
colours' at all
times.50 The claimant, an exemplary employee who had provided the
employer with twenty years of service, objected to the make-up requirement,
on
the grounds of the alleged degradation that compliance with the obligation
entailed.
The Court was presented with two alternative grounds upon which the
dress policy was argued to amount to discrimination because of
sex. First, it
was asserted that, in accordance with established precedent, the female dress
code contravened Title VII through imposing an unequal burden on female
employees. Secondly, the Ninth Circuit was urged to apply the Price
Waterhouse principle to recognise the illegality of the make-up rule
pursuant to its requirement that women conform to sex stereotypes as a condition
of employment. These contrasting approaches will now be discussed in
turn.
Unequal Burdens Approach
American jurisprudence has established that a sex-differentiated dress code
will amount to a less favourable term or condition of
employment under Title
VII, if compliance with the overall gender based dress code as a whole can
be seen to be unduly burdensome for one sex. Bearing in mind
that this approach
is simply a judicial interpretation of what constitutes less favourable terms of
employment and conditions of
work,51 it is apparent this approach
would be open for the New Zealand courts to adopt under New Zealand's comparable
legislation.
The unequal burdens approach has not in fact always prevailed in
American law. An examination of the vast American jurisprudence surrounding
the
legality of sex-differentiated dress codes reveals a significant maturation of
the judicial approach to the issue over recent
decades. In the embryonic stages
of the dress code jurisprudence, judicial reliance was placed on the
intrinsically mutable nature
of dress requirements in order to successfully
defeat discrimination claims,52 and aggrieved claimants were
confronted with a virtually insurmountable hurdle.
However, with the
increasing recognition that the scope of the legislative protection provided by
Title VII extended beyond the protection of only immutable
characteristics, the previous judicial dependence on the concept of mutability
to
defeat dress code discrimination claims began to be superseded by the
alternative inquiry as to whether a sex-differentiated dress
code could be seen
to unduly burden one sex over the other.53 Thus, requirements where a
workplace uniform was imposed on female employees alone,54 or where
the requisite female uniform was sexually revealing,55 or where only
female employees were required to comply with workplace weight
requirements56 were all found to be unduly burdensome. A salient
feature of this judicial approach is that the effect of the dress code as a
whole
is examined, rather than the particular appearance requirement that may be
the subject of complaint. While no clear judicial explanation
has been offered
for the underlying reasoning behind this principle,57 it would
appear, as explained below, to be driven by a judicial reluctance to recognise
the viability of such discrimination claims.
The judicial proclivity
towards comparing the purported burdens associated with compliance with a
sex-differentiated dress code was
formalised by the Ninth Circuit in Frank v
United Airlines.58 Illustrating a tacit acceptance of
gender differentiated appearance standards, the Court established the governing
principle that
gendered appearance codes which impose 'different but essentially
equal burdens on men and women' will not amount to direct discrimination
under
Title VII.59 Thus, although the court in Jespersen
was presented with the proposition that a sex-based difference in appearance
standards should of itself amount to direct sex discrimination,
such an
assertion was rejected. Rather, the Court held that the unequal burdens analysis
was required in order to establish that
the complainant was treated less
favourably with regards to her terms and conditions of employment.60
The Jespersen majority's unquestioning acceptance of this
formulation has now firmly entrenched the unequal burdens test as the guiding
framework
to be followed in dress code discrimination claims in the United
States.
Despite the majority's explicit endorsement of the unequal burdens
approach in Jespersen, their subsequent application of the test vividly
illustrates the inherent difficulties that arise with this judicial formulation;
and the intrinsically amorphous nature of the test was revealed through the
Court's preferred construction of the respective 'burdens'
to be compared under
the male and female dress codes. Opting for a narrow construction of the
'burdens' that were to be measured,
the majority focused solely on the monetary
and temporal constraints created by compliance with the differing dress
policies.61 Following this approach, the female dress policy was held
to impose no greater burden on female employees than that experienced by
their
male counterparts. Although the majority accepted that the policies contained
different grooming standards for male and female
employees, it was nevertheless
argued that when the overall codes were respectively considered neither could be
seen to be more onerous
for one sex than the other.62 Unfortunately,
no comprehensive analysis accompanied this finding. Rather, reliance was placed
on the lack of documentary evidence
provided by the claimant in regards to the
time and cost requirements necessitated by compliance with the dress
policy.63
The possibility that the unequal burdens test could
potentially be satisfied by clear and compelling evidence of both monetary and
temporal disparities was left open by the majority, but the majority's clear
reluctance to countenance that the time and cost constraints
of the 'Personal
Best' code could have satisfied the unequal burdens test was questionable. When
a comparative analysis of the male
and female dress codes is undertaken, in the
fiscal and temporal terms prescribed by the majority, a stark discrepancy in the
burdens
associated with the respective appearance standards is in fact revealed.
As acknowledged in the pragmatic dissent of Judge Kozinski,
when a comparison is
made between the differing grooming standards for the hands, hair and face, it
is indisputable that a greater
burden was created for female
employees.64 As cogently argued by the Judge, any appearance standard
that requires female employees to wear facial make-up creates a significant
temporal burden, as the application of cosmetic make-up involves 'an intricate
and painstaking process [that] requires considerable
time and
care'.65 The financial expenditure associated with the required use
of cosmetic products was also alluded to by Judge Kozinski, who appeared
perplexed that the majority could be in 'any doubt that putting on makeup costs
money'.66 The judge's reasoning here is surely persuasive. It is well
established that the economic burdens associated with make-up use can
be
substantial,67 and given that there was no equivalent expenditure
required of male employees under the 'Personal Best' policy, the greater
economic
burden should have been self-evident. If the unequal burdens test were
to be accepted, it is clear that the dress code at issue in
Jespersen
should have satisfied the test's requirements.
While the dress code
examined by the Ninth Circuit in Jespersen could readily have satisfied
the unequal burdens test, it must be emphasised that the foundations of the
actual test itself are questionable,
if not fundamentally flawed, and that
judicial adherence to this approach is undesirable. First, the focus by way of
comparison on
the total effect of the dress code for women when compared with
the effect of the dress code for men is obscure. As argued by Judge
Pregerson,
the fact that a dress policy contains sex-differentiated requirements for both
male and female employees should not exempt
a particular requirement from
scrutiny.68
Secondly, the test itself is plagued with imprecision,
as no definitive guidance as to the parameters of the burdens to be measured
currently exists. Surprisingly, the vagueness surrounding the intended scope of
the test has not perturbed the judiciary but rather
been seemingly embraced. The
remarks of the lower Court that there was no need to clarify the boundaries of
the judicial approach,
as it did not 'equate to an exact science yielding
results with mathematical certainty'69 illustrates well the lack of
judicial desire to clarify the parameters of the 'burdens' to be compared. This
judicial ambivalence
is unsatisfactory: the inherent flexibility of the test's
boundaries grants the courts too much license to allow subjective policy
matters
to influence the scope of the test's parameters, and the outcomes of any
judicial application of the approach will inevitably
be highly
variable.70 Such concerns are well illustrated by the Jespersen
decision itself. Although the consideration of the demeaning nature of a
gender based dress code had previously fallen within the
scope of a 'burden' to
be compared,71 the uncertainty surrounding the test's intended scope
enabled the majority in Jespersen to restrict their consideration to
concerns of a purely fiscal and temporal nature.
It must also be emphasised that the majority's narrow construction of the
'burdens' to be compared under the approach is inherently
problematic from a
normative perspective. In particular, the Court, by limiting its comparative
analysis to a consideration of time
and cost constraints, was able to eschew any
examination of the implicit harms that can be occasioned through requiring
employee
compliance with the dominant norms of femininity. For instance, this
restricted construction enabled the majority both to overlook
the claimant's
sense of ignominy, suffered as a result of the compulsory make-up requirement,
and to evade exploration of the wider
normative underpinnings that such a
requirement entailed.72 This approach, through enabling the Court to
successfully side-step any normative discussion of the desirability of gendered
appearance
standards, seemingly ignores Title VII's fundamental aim of
challenging harmful employment practices.
It has accordingly been suggested
that the unequal burdens test should be expanded to include consideration of the
underlying harms
occasioned by the perpetuation of dominant gender norms within
its parameters.73 This argument does have some merit. Nevertheless,
it must be noted it fails to identify the core difficulty that arises with the
unequal burdens test. Any argument that advocates the expansion of the test to
include consideration of intangible burdens within
its parameters implicitly
accepts the validity of this form of comparative assessment. Such unquestioning
acceptance of the test's
foundations is dubious, as it is clear that any
attempts to compare the purported burdens that arise with differing dress codes
will
inevitably require recourse to some form of arbitrary
nominalism.74 While it may be feasible to attempt to compare the time
and costs associated with compliance, which still requires the court to engage
in a somewhat protracted fact-finding inquiry,75 any suggestion that
a court is ostensibly able to measure and weigh the subjective degradation that
may be experienced under each
gender based dress code is untenable. Attempts to
compare the severity of the implicit harm that may be occasioned through a
restriction
on a male employee's hair length, with the requirement that a female
employee wear make-up will be entirely dependent upon the judiciary's
subjective
inclinations. However, it can be conceded that a judicial inquiry into the
normative foundations of an appearance standard,
under the more expansive
approach, is certainly a more attractive option than adherence to the narrow
approach advocated by the majority
in Jespersen.
It must also be noted that the test operates upon the illogical premise that any burden associated with a sex-differentiated dress code is able to be considered as inherently benign if it can purportedly be compared to a restriction in the contrasting dress code for the other sex.76 As will be discussed below, this illustrates well the significant difficulties that arise with the formal equality construct that permeates anti-discrimination law. The broad method of comparative analysis adopted by the Court demonstrated a judicial acceptance that any gender based dress requirements imposed upon the other sex are sufficiently similar in nature to be included within the comparison required to establish that less favourable treatment has occurred.77 Such a premise offers little hope for any sense of progression in sex discrimination jurisprudence. This comparative approach offers no protection for employees whose gendered identities do not conform with societal norms, and it fails to allow for consideration of the undesirable ideologies propagated by the dominant norms surrounding female appearance. It would be unfortunate indeed if the New Zealand courts sought to adopt this flawed approach.
Sex Stereotyping Approach
As discussed above, the Supreme Court's judgment in Price Waterhouse
provided an important and overt judicial recognition that any condition of
employment which required compliance with gender norms
could constitute
discrimination on the grounds of 'sex'.78 At first sight, this
principle would appear to be of significant utility to employees seeking to
challenge dress codes which encompass
stereotypical gendered ideologies. It is
clear that through proscribing the perpetuation of sex-stereotyping in the
workforce the
Supreme Court can be seen to have 'articulated a doctrinal
framework' that provided federal courts with the tools to identify and
proscribe
any workplace rules that operated to reinforce gendered
expectations.79 Indeed, under the Price Waterhouse framework,
it could easily be contended that an appearance requirement that requires a
female employee to comply with the dominant
norms of femininity would amount to
a 'less favourable' term or condition of employment that arose because of the
employee's sex.
The Ninth Circuit in Jespersen was presented with such an argument. In
contrast to the District Court's rejection of this proposition, the Court did
concede that
any appearance standard encompassing 'impermissible sex
stereotyping' could be challenged under the Price Waterhouse
decision.80 Such a judicial acknowledgment would at first sight
appear to have been a significant step forward in dress code discrimination
jurisprudence.
However, any aspirations of truly noteworthy progression were
rendered hollow by the majority's narrow interpretation of the 'impermissible
sex stereotyping' standard. By emphasising that the 'Personal Best' policy was
neither 'sexually provocative', nor driven by an intention
to 'stereotype women
as sex objects', the majority indicated that the 'impermissible sex
stereotyping' standard should be confined
to dress standards that explicitly
sexualised female employees.81 Such a proposition is rather puzzling,
and is irreconcilable with the underpinning rationale of the Price Waterhouse
decision that gender must be irrelevant to employment decisions.
Additionally, the majority's failure to contemplate that the facial
make-up
requirement was driven by gendered stereotyping is at complete odds with the
Price Waterhouse decision itself. As the Supreme Court had viewed the
suggestion that the female claimant wear make-up to be evidence of sex
stereotyping,
it is certainly surprising that the compulsory make-up requirement
at issue in Jespersen was not subjected to greater scrutiny.82
The Jespersen decision thus appears to narrow the scope of the Price
Waterhouse principle for no apparent reason.
The majority's failure in
Jespersen to consider the potentially pernicious effects of the
employer's facial make-up requirement was made possible by their assertion that
the requirement should not be considered in isolation, but rather that the
sex-stereotyping that was evident in the policy as a whole
should be considered.
Following this approach, it was reasoned by the majority that in light of the
unisex uniform included within
the policy there was no evidence that the policy
as a whole was adopted to 'make women bartenders conform to a commonly accepted
stereotypical image of what women should wear'.83 The majority's
approach is troubling, and offers little hope for ensuring the attainment of
female equality in the workplace. As
argued by Judge Pregerson in his dissent,
the majority's refusal to give separate consideration to the make-up requirement
enabled
otherwise impermissible gender stereotypes to be
neutralised.84
Incontrovertibly, the facial make-up requirement
could have been subjected to challenge under the Price Waterhouse
principle. As acknowledged in Judge Pregerson's dissent, any make-up
requirement is inevitably driven by sexual stereotyping, because
it produces the
'inescapable message, that women's undoctored faces compare unfavourably to men,
because of the cultural assumption
and gender based stereotype, that women's
faces are incomplete, unattractive, or unprofessional without full
make-up'.85
As such, the normative underpinnings of make-up use are disturbing and well established. Make-up as a form of cosmetic adornment originated from the intention to replicate female sexual arousal,86 and the prevalent use of cosmetic make-up in Western society is now widely acknowledged to be driven by the stereotypical assumption that women should appear ornamental in appearance, so as to appear attractive to men.87 Accordingly, any employment requirement necessitating the use of make-up during working hours propagates stereotypical notions of femininity which will inevitably hinder the effective advancement of women in the workforce.
Price Waterhouse and Transgendered Rights
The majority's assiduous attempts in Jespersen to narrow the
application of Price Waterhouse not only lacked a sound legal base but
appeared to be fundamentally at odds with the developing American jurisprudence
surrounding
transgendered rights in employment. Historically, federal courts
have been reluctant to hold that employment discrimination on the
grounds of an
employee's transgender identity could constitute discrimination on the grounds
of 'sex', because of the judicial belief
that Title VII was only intended
to prohibit 'discrimination against women because they are women, and men
because they are men'.88 However, the judicial treatment of
transgendered discrimination has recently become marked by an increasingly
liberal attitude. In
the seminal decision of Smith v City of
Salem,89 the Sixth Circuit of the Court of Appeals
indicated that any judicial denial of the protection of transgendered
individuals under
Title VII had been 'eviscerated' by the decision of
Price Waterhouse.90 The Court upheld a sex
discrimination claim brought by a male fire-fighter, diagnosed with gender
identity disorder, who was dismissed
from employment after informing his
employers of his wish to present as a woman at work. It was argued by the Court
that 'discrimination
against a plaintiff who is transsexual, and fails to act or
identify with his or her gender, is no different from the discrimination
directed against Ann Hopkins in Price Waterhouse, who, in
sex-stereotypical terms, did not act like a woman'.91 This reasoning
is compelling. In light of the growing judicial acceptance that Price
Waterhouse can be invoked to protect transgender individuals who do not
conform to societal gender norms, it appears all the more anomalous that
under
Jespersen such individuals could nevertheless be dismissed for a failure
to comply with gendered appearance standards
Bona Fide Occupational Qualification
The Ninth Circuit's questionable application of the unequal burdens test, and
its narrow reading of the Price Waterhouse principle, resulted in a
finding that facial make-up requirement did not contravene Title VII's
prohibition of discrimination on the grounds of sex. Accordingly, there was
no need for the respondent employer to attempt to justify
its dress policy under
the statutory 'Bona Fide Occupational Qualification' (BFOQ) defence.
Nevertheless, in light of the unpersuasive
reasoning employed by the majority in
Jespersen, the potential application of the BFOQ defence to the
Jespersen case merits some comment, for while this defence is far wider
than the equivalent exception provided by s 27 of the Human Rights Act
199392 the established principles surrounding the
justification might provide some assistance to the New Zealand
courts.93
Title VII provides that employment discrimination
which occurs 'because of sex' will be justified in situations where the
'discrimination is
reasonably necessary to the operation of the business or
enterprise'.94 In contrast to the judicial ambivalence discernable in
the approach taken by federal courts towards the recognition of sex
discrimination
in the workplace, the BFOQ defence is treated with a significant
degree of respect. The Supreme Court has stipulated that the justification
is
'meant to be an extremely narrow exception to the general prohibition of
discrimination on the basis of sex',95 and Federal courts have taken
heed of this rigorous instruction. It is now well established that an employer's
desire to accede to
the demands of customer preferences does not satisfy the
stringency of the narrow exception.96 For instance, in the
influential decision of Wilson v Southwest Airlines,97
it was confirmed that any judicial inquiry under the BFOQ defence must focus
'on the particular service provided and the job tasks
and functions involved,
not the [employer's] business goal'.98 It was also emphasised by the
court that the BFOQ provision cannot be employed to justify the exploitation of
female sexuality to
ensure the generation of profit.99 Accordingly,
the employer's claim that the financial viability of its airline was dependent
upon hiring solely young and attractive
females was emphatically
rejected.
While the scope of the BFOQ justification has been subjected to
considerable interpretative rigidity by the courts, various grounds
upon which
the defence can succeed have been established.100 Of most
significance to our discussion of gendered dress policies, is the judicial
acceptance that female sexuality can be legitimately
exploited in instances
where the primary purpose of the business is sexual entertainment. For instance,
in St Cross v Playboy Club of New York,101 it was
accepted that the employer's practice of hiring solely female waitresses, who
were required to wear revealing 'bunny' outfits
whilst serving cocktails, was
justified on the basis that the dominant purpose of the Playboy Club was to
'titillate and entice male
customers'.102 Thus, sexually charged
uniforms would be permissible in businesses that aimed to provide some form of
sexual gratification for their
customers.
Examining these established
precedents, it emerges that the employer in Jespersen would have
struggled to surmount the hurdle posed by the BFOQ defence. As the bartenders'
job description was to 'maintain courteous
professional working relationships
with customers and co-workers, and to make drinks effectively and
efficiently',103 it becomes clear that the purported need for female
staff to maintain a traditionally feminine appearance could not be seen to fall
within the essence of the job tasks and functions required by the employer.
Indeed, when the potential applicability of the BFOQ
justification to the
Jespersen case is examined, the absurdity of the compulsory make-up
requirement is well and truly highlighted.
V. ENGLISH JURISPRUDENCE
The limited English jurisprudence that has developed in regards to the
legality of gender specific dress codes reveals a similar judicial
reluctance to
countenance the notion that gender based appearance standards could contravene
England's legislative framework on discrimination.
Under s 1(1)(a) of the Sex
Discrimination Act 1975,104 discrimination is defined as
'less favourable treatment' on the grounds of 'sex', and this definition of
discrimination is thus analogous
to the proscription of 'less favourable' terms
of employment and conditions of work under s 22(1)(b) of the Human Rights Act
1993. The leading English decision on the discriminatory effects of gender
based dress codes was delivered by the Court of Appeal in Smith v
Safeway,105 and here the Court was presented with the
opportunity to examine the validity of the seminal approach taken towards such
policies
by the Employment Appeals Tribunal in Schmidt v Austicks
Bookshops.106 Phillips LJ delivered the leading judgment in
Safeway, with separate concurring judgments being delivered by
Peter-Gibson LJ and Leggatt LJ
The approach taken by the Employment Appeals Tribunal in Schmidt, was strongly endorsed by their Lordships, and the reasoning employed by the Tribunal in that decision therefore needs to be examined first.
Schmidt v Austicks Bookshops
The Schmidt decision involved the dismissal of a female sales assistant for non-compliance with her employer's dress code that prohibited female employees from wearing trousers at work. Unsurprisingly, this restriction did not apply to male employees. Dismissing the complainant's claim, the Employment Appeals Tribunal urged that an expansive approach towards the establishment of 'less favourable treatment' should be taken.107 Noting that it was not possible to identify a comparable dress restriction that applied to male employees, it was nevertheless held that through engaging in a comparative analysis of the restrictions encompassed within the contrasting dress codes it was 'possible to approach the matter a little more broadly'.108 Following this approach, it was reasoned that because the wearing of T-shirts, and other 'out of the way' clothing was prohibited for male employees, the employer, 'as far as a comparison was possible ... treated both female and male staff alike, in that both sexes were restricted in the choice of clothing for wear whilst at work'.109 It can thus be seen that a notable feature of the Employment Appeals Tribunal's judgment was its refusal to consider the form and extent of the restrictions imposed under the respective dress codes. Such an approach meant that the Employment Appeals Tribunal's preferred form of comparative analysis was pitched at an extremely high level of abstraction.
Smith v Safeway
Two decades after the delivery of the Schmidt decision, the Court of
Appeal was presented with the opportunity to reconsider the broad method of
comparison favoured by the Employment
Appeals Tribunal. In Safeway, the
male complainant had been dismissed from employment as a delicatessen assistant,
having failed to comply with the employer's appearance
standard prohibiting male
employees from having hair that fell below collar length. As female assistants
were permitted to have long
hair (provided it was clipped back during working
hours), the employer's restriction was driven by appearance concerns rather than
those of health and safety. A discrimination claim under s (1)(1)(a) of the
Sex Discrimination Act was duly lodged.
Dismissing the complainant's
sex discrimination claim, the Court of Appeal affirmed the Schmidt
approach and clarified the principles to be derived from the decision. While
the majority of the Employment Appeals Tribunal in the
Safeway case had
taken the somewhat innovative approach of attempting to distinguish Schmidt
on the grounds that the hair restriction would impact the male claimant's
appearance outside working hours, such an intrusion being
deemed to be
'fundamentally unfair',110 the Court of Appeal was sceptical of that
reasoning. Rather, the Court stated that Schmidt's application extended
beyond the simply ephemeral to include the more permanent of appearance
characteristics.111 The distinction that had been drawn by the
Tribunal between differing forms of appearance was thus discredited.
The
broad comparative approach advocated in Schmidt was explicitly endorsed
by the Court in Safeway, and Phillips LJ accepted that any comparison
undertaken of differing dress standards should not be taken garment by garment
but rather
that a comparative 'package approach' should be taken of the policies
as a whole.112 The emphasis placed by the Employment Appeals Tribunal
in Schmidt on the need to compare the restrictions imposed under each
code, was similarly reflected in Phillips LJ's finding that as the employer
had
taken an 'even-handed' approach towards the dress policies by imposing
restrictions on the hair-styles of both men and women
the Sex Discrimination
Act had not been contravened.113 As to what exactly would
constitute the specific hair restrictions for females was left unclear -
although, apparently influenced
by having viewed a 'variety of unconventional
hairstyles' while 'walk[ing] through Camden Lock market on a Saturday
afternoon', his
Lordship did assert that female employees would hypothetically
have been prevented from 'shaving part of [their] scalp' under the
dress
code.114 The Court's reasoning thus reflected the same unwillingness
witnessed in the Employment Appeals Tribunal decision in Schmidt to delve
into a deeper examination of both the type and extent of restrictions imposed
under the contrasting codes.
Although the reasoning of the Court in
Safeway has not been the subject of sustained judicial or academic
examination, the intended scope of the 'even-handed' requirement stipulated
by
the Court was the subject of consideration by the Employment Appeals Tribunal in
the later case of Department for Work and Pensions v
Thompson.115 In Thompson, the Employment Appeals
Tribunal was presented with the proposition, advanced by the Manchester
Employment Tribunal (MET) that the
'even-handed' approach prescribed by the
Court of Appeal necessitated the imposition of an employment dress code
requiring both sexes
to wear clothing of a similar kind. Following this
interpretation, the MET had upheld a sex discrimination claim brought by a male
administrative assistant, who had been disciplined for non-compliance with his
employer's gendered dress code requiring male employees
to wear a collar and tie
at work. As the female dress code simply required female employees to 'dress
appropriately and to a similar
standard', the Tribunal's restricted
interpretation of the 'even-handed' formulation had resulted in its recognition
of the sex discrimination
claim, on the grounds that women had a greater choice
of options for workplace attire as they were not required to wear clothing
of a
particular kind at work.116 Overturning the MET's decision, the
Employment Appeals Tribunal opined that the evenhandedness stipulation simply
required the tribunal
to investigate whether 'applying standards of conventional
dress wear, the level of smartness which [the employer] required of all
its
staff could only be achieved for men by requiring them to wear a collar and
tie'.117 This broader interpretation, it could be commented, was more
consistent with the higher level of comparative abstraction favoured
by the
Court of Appeal in Safeway.
Problems with the Safeway Approach
While the Court of Appeal's decision in Safeway remains the governing
approach to be taken towards dress code discrimination claims under English law,
fundamental difficulties arise
with the legal analysis employed by the Court in
the decision. First of all, the Court in Safeway overlooked the
definitive 'but for' causal test established by the House of Lords in James v
Eastleigh.118 In a pivotal statement, Lord Goff in
James had stipulated that the court must determine whether a complainant
would 'have received the same treatment from the defendant but
for his or her
sex'.119 Under a straightforward application of the 'but for' test, a
claim of sex discrimination could readily have been founded in
Safeway.
It has been mistakenly assumed that the complainant's
dismissal in Safeway amounted to 'less favourable treatment' that would
not have occurred 'but for' his sex.120 This argument, though,
overlooks the fact that 'less favourable treatment' under the Sex
Discrimination Act is a test that needs to be established before the
examination of any employment detriment suffered, as a result of this treatment,
is undertaken.121 However, as the denial of a choice that holds value
for the complainant does constitute 'less favourable treatment', under the
Act,122 the hair restriction imposed on the male employee in
Safeway can easily be seen to fall within the scope of s
(1)(1)(a).123 Quite simply, the restriction imposed on the male's
hair length would not have occurred 'but for' his sex.
Additionally, the Court of Appeal neglected to follow the approach taken by
their Lordships in James with respect to the appropriate formulation of a
comparator to whom a sex discrimination claimant must be compared when
determining
whether 'less favourable' treatment has occurred. In James,
their Lordships emphasised that when the comparison to establish the
occurrence of 'less favourable treatment' is undertaken, any
gender based
criterion imposed on the other sex should not be included within the scope of
the comparison.124 The Safeway approach cannot be reconciled
with this imperative. Following the James analysis, the gender based
restrictions imposed on the hair styles of female employees in Safeway
should not have been considered in the Court's examination as to whether
'less favourable treatment' could be seen to have occurred.125 The
Court's failure to consider the implications of the James decision is
inexplicable.
The clear discrepancy that arises between the James and
Safeway approaches was briefly alluded to by the Employment Appeals
Tribunal in the Thompson decision. Observing that the causal 'but for'
test could not be used to establish less favourable treatment in and of itself,
the
Employment Appeals Tribunal was careful to emphasise that the causal test
was to be applied only after the occurrence of less favourable
treatment had
been established.126 However, the Employment Appeals Tribunal
declined to provide any comment on the general inconsistency that currently
exists between
the Safeway and James principles. Rather, it was
acknowledged by the Employment Appeals Tribunal that 'it should be left to the
Court of Appeal to decide
what impact the James case had on the
principles enunciated in the Safeway case'.127 The law in
England thus remains inconsistent.
It is not only the legal analysis of the
Safeway decision that gives cause for concern: the normative implications
of the decision are equally worrying. A salient feature of the Court
of Appeal's
decision in Safeway was the Court's explicit endorsement of employment
dress codes that embraced conventional appearance standards. Phillips LJ's
affirmation
that gendered dress codes enforcing a 'common principle' of
'conventionality' could not be seen to be discriminatory was
unfortunate,128 and the unquestioning judicial acceptance of the
standard of conventionality seemingly contradicts the overriding goal of the
Sex Discrimination Act, which is to combat societal adherence to
traditional sex stereotypes.129
The potential discrepancy between
the employer imposition of gender based dress standards, and the normative aims
of the Sex Discrimination Act had been judicially recognised before the
Safeway decision. Early concerns were voiced by the Industrial Tribunal,
in the unreported decision of Rewcastle v Safeway Plc,130
that a 'policy which is designed to mirror 'conventional differences'
between the sexes cannot be reconciled with the underlying rationale
of the sex
discrimination legislation which is to challenge traditional assumptions about
sexes, not only as to their roles in society,
and the tasks they perform, but
also as to their appearance and dress'.131 The reasoning is surely
persuasive, and Phillips LJ's explicit rejection of the Industrial Tribunals'
unease132 revealed a seeming indifference to the fact that the
conceptual underpinnings of the Sex Discrimination Act cannot be easily
reconciled with the judicial acceptance of conventional appearance standards in
the workplace.
Upon close examination of the Safeway decision it also
becomes apparent that the Court's conception of conventionality encompassed
highly questionable ideals of gender
normativity. Phillips LJ's contention that
a purportedly conventional female dress code could include '18 inch hair,
earrings and
lipstick'133 shows the underlying dangers of employing
an inherently fluid standard that is so obviously prone to manipulation at the
judiciary's
whim. The concept of conventionality employed by Phillips LJ
illustrates that the entirely subjective opinions of judges will permeate
and
shape the standard of conventionality which is to be treated as the benchmark of
apparent fairness. The approach thus enables
the courts to bypass any
consideration of the harms that can be occasioned by the perpetuation of
gendered stereotyping in the workplace,
and it should be eschewed by the New
Zealand courts.
VI. THE FAVOURED MODEL OF JUDICIAL COMPARISON
The Comparative Approach
The comparative model endorsed by the Court of Appeal in Safeway
remains the guiding approach for dress code discrimination claims under
English law, and it is clear the abstracted comparative approach
favoured by the
Court bears a striking similarity to the unequal burdens test applied by the
Ninth Circuit in Jespersen. Both approaches allow the courts to avoid any
sustained analysis of the particular dress or grooming requirement that is the
subject
of complaint, through focusing on a wider comparative analysis of the
restrictions encompassed within the dress codes as a whole.
The Safeway
approach can thus be subjected to many of the same criticisms leveled above
at its American counterpart. As the Safeway analysis requires the courts
to compare the 'restrictions' imposed under contrasting dress codes, without
providing any guidance as
to what such restrictions may entail, the framework
enables the courts to avoid any normative evaluation of the implicit harms
occasioned
by the imposition of gender based dress codes in the
workplace.
Although the Safeway form of comparison is analogous to the
unequal burdens test, it must be emphasised it remains significantly less
developed. And as
no incisive analysis of the form of restrictions to be
compared was required by the Court of Appeal, its preferred form of comparison
was pitched at a significantly higher level of abstraction than that adopted by
the Ninth Circuit in Jespersen. In short, exactly what may comprise such
a restriction under the Court of Appeal's approach remains elusive, and a
greater amount
of judicial flexibility will thus be accorded to
sex-differentiated dress codes in England. This is well illustrated by the fact
that while the imposition of uniforms on only female employees has been regarded
as unduly burdensome under the American jurisprudence,134 a
compulsory dress requirement that obliged only female nurses to wear a starch
linen cap was upheld under the broad Schmidt approach.135
A
significant issue that surprisingly has not been raised in previous academic
comment is that the concerns arising from the abstracted
form of comparative
analysis in both the American and English jurisdictions bring to the fore wider
difficulties arising from the
general conception of formal equality as a whole.
The formal equality principle is predicated upon the Aristotelian ideal that
like
should be treated alike, and this normative aspiration underpins the
concept of direct discrimination.136 At first sight this ideal
appears to be both morally sound and laudable. However, any hopes that this form
of equality will achieve
liberal aspirations are rendered illusory upon closer
examination. Acute difficulties arise with the definition of what constitutes
the intrinsically nebulous concept of 'likeness', as any attempt at definition
of likeness is bound to result in tautology.137
The lack of any
substantive justification underpinning the normative foundations of the formal
equality construct presents significant
obstacles to the goal of ensuring that
social justice is achieved under anti-discrimination legislation. As the
conception of formal
equality is predicated upon the objective of consistency in
treatment, the normative aims of this construct simply amount to a principle
of
relativity containing no substantive underpinnings.138 Thus, under
the conception of formal equality there is no difference between treating
individuals equally badly or equally well.139 It can accordingly be
argued that the sheer illogicality of the fact that an employer, under the
Jespersen or Safeway approach, is granted the license to balance
the restrictions associated with differing gender based dress codes is
symptomatic of
the wider difficulties that plague the general concept of formal
equality as a whole.
The greatest difficulty associated with the formal equality construct is the
need for a form of comparison to be undertaken between
the complainant and
another individual in similarly situated circumstances.140 Such a
task is necessitated by the construct's normative underpinnings, and the very
notion that like must be treated alike inevitably
requires the courts to select
an appropriate comparator to whom the claimant can be compared. The freedom
given to judges in the
construction of a comparator gives cause for concern, as
the judicial determination of an appropriate comparator inevitably requires
a
'complex value judgment as to which of the myriad of differences between two
individuals are relevant, and which are irrelevant'.141
The fact
that hidden moral and ideological underpinnings will inevitably influence the
form of comparison to be undertaken is seen
in the international jurisprudence
surrounding gendered appearance standards. And, as discussed above, the judicial
preference towards
a broad form of comparative analysis enables the courts to
avoid considering the possibility that an appearance requirement, incorporated
within a wider dress policy, could contravene sex discrimination legislation.
The courts' implicit acceptance that differing gender
based appearance
standards, imposed on employees of the other sex, are sufficiently alike to be
included within the comparison required
for the establishment of less favourable
treatment142 means the substantive justifications of such
restrictions are never adequately explored. As there is no good reason why the
courts
should consider the net equality of a sex-differentiated dress code,
instead of examining the particular dress requirement that is
the subject of
complaint,143 the judicial tendency to favour the more abstracted
form of analysis is revealing. The reluctance to narrow the comparison to be
undertaken indicates a deep-seated aversion towards the recognition of such
discrimination claims, and it thus becomes necessary
to explore the
jurisprudential foundations of this judicial unease and to examine whether the
concerns have any validity.
VII. POLICY CONSIDERATIONS
Acceptance of Societal Norms
An underlying judicial assumption that the perpetuation of prevailing
societal norms in the workplace is unobjectionable can be perceived
in the
American and English jurisprudence surrounding sex-differentiated dress
discrimination claims, and a clear judicial reluctance
to interfere with
prevailing hegemonic ideologies can be discerned from the case law analysed
above. The earliest stages of the American
jurisprudence was noteworthy for its
avowed acceptance of the purported innocuous nature of societal norms. For
example, the assertion
in the early case of Carroll v Federal Savings
Bank144 that a dress code with some justification 'in commonly
accepted social norms' was acceptable,145 illustrates well the
prevailing judicial attitude. While such judicial sentiments were not as
pronounced in the Jespersen decision, the majority's intuitive acceptance
of the apparent innocuousness of dominant gendered norms was still evident; and
Justice
Schroeder's refusal to contemplate that a compulsory make-up requirement
could constitute a form of 'impermissible sex stereotyping'
provided an
illuminating illustration of the majority's unquestioning acceptance of
prevailing gendered appearance standards.
Judicial receptiveness towards the
permissibility of gendered norms remains even more explicit under English law.
As seen above, the
conventionality threshold established by the Court of Appeal
in Safeway ensures that dress codes encompassing dominant gender norms
will be viewed as unobjectionable. Unfortunately, any judicial support
of the
viability of gender norms serves to effectively reinforce their validity, and
societal progression and development is thereby
inhibited.146
Although it has been argued that the task of challenging societal norms should
not fall to the judiciary,147 such assertions fail to recognise that
a quintessential aim of all anti-discrimination legislation, which the judiciary
is required
to interpret and apply, is to challenge traditional assumptions and
prejudices. A broad and purposive construction of such legislation
would
therefore require a deeper questioning of the validity of dominant gender norms,
rather than an unquestioning acceptance of
their permissibility.
Inability to Comprehend Gender Fluidity
A deep-seated judicial unwillingness to disrupt the dichotomous boundaries of
gender normativity can also be discerned from an examination
of the
international jurisprudence discussed above. Although the concern voiced in an
earlier federal decision that abolition of
gender based dress codes would result
in male employees 'minc[ing] around in high heels',148 was not so
colourfully expressed by the majority in Jespersen, lingering concerns
about gender transgressions in the workplace were still evident in the judgment.
For instance, the reasoning that
the sex-differentiated grooming standards were
necessary to create a 'professional' look for the bartenders,149
illustrated the majority's inability to embrace the existence of gender fluidity
in the workplace.
In Safeway the Court of Appeal was significantly
less restrained in communicating its unease surrounding the occurrence of
workplace cross-dressing.
Phillip LJ's highly questionable assertion that the
necessity of gender based dress codes was obvious, in view of the fact that men
could otherwise be subjected to the requirement of having to wear '18 inch hair,
make-up, and high heels'150 to work, was certainly revealing.
Notwithstanding the irrationality of the assumption that recognition of a sex
discrimination claim
would inevitably result in compulsory cross-dressing in the
workplace, Phillip LJ's analysis unwittingly disclosed a deeply ingrained
perception that the practice of cross-dressing was simply unfathomable.
In
light of the progressive liberality that has begun to pervade international
jurisprudence surrounding transgender rights in employment,
the judicial disdain
accorded to gendered presentations that destabilise hegemonic gender ideologies
is rapidly losing force. As
discussed above, some Federal courts in the United
States are beginning to engage in a broad construction of Title VII in
order to provide protection from discrimination to transgendered employees.
Moreover, the European Court of Justice's recognition
that protection of
discrimination on the grounds of gender re-assignment should fall within the
scope of the Equal Treatment Directive's
prohibition of sex
discrimination,151 led to the enactment of the Sex Discrimination
(Gender Reassignment Regulations) 1999 in the United Kingdom.152 As
the protection from discrimination provided by the legislative amendment extends
to the pre-surgical period of transition, the
concerns over men wearing high
heels voiced in Safeway appears all the more anomalous.153 A
fundamental chasm currently exists between the restrictive dress code
jurisprudence, and the progressive attitude that has begun
to be taken towards
transgender rights in the international arena.
Employer's Right to Control Business Image
At first glance, the current anomaly that exists between the judicial
recognition of transgender rights in employment and the contrasting
rejection of
gendered appearance standard discrimination claims would appear entirely
incomprehensible. However, upon a deeper examination
of the current
jurisprudence a clearer picture begins to emerge.
In the United States,
evidence of a significant judicial deference towards an employer's prerogative
to control its business image
surfaces from an exploration of the case-law, and
the purported need for an employer to be free to create a particular business
image,
through the imposition of gender based dress codes, has long pervaded
American judicial thinking. Recourse to such a policy concern
was well
illustrated by comments made in the early decision of Fagan v National Cash
Register,154 to the effect that 'no facet of business life
is more important than a company's place in public estimation'.155 As
the unfortunate perception that the 'spectre of men in dresses' may be 'commerce
threatening'156 still lingers amongst the American judiciary, this
could explain the underlying judicial reluctance to embrace any approach that
accepts the possibility of fluidity in gender presentation occurring in the
workplace. The pivotal role that an employer's business
image plays in the
imposition of gender differentiated dress policies was also demonstrated in the
Jespersen decision itself. The overt aim of the 'Personal Best' policy
was to maintain a 'brand standard of excellence,' and the majority's
emphasis
that the policy was imposed within 'the context of the entertainment
industry'157 illustrated belief in the importance of an employer's
brand image. The clear judicial acquiescence towards the protection of the
employer's
business judgment is surprising. Under a broad and purposive
construction of human rights legislation, the employee's right to remain
free
from discrimination would surely need to be accorded paramountcy. Additionally,
judicial consideration of the effect that the
appearance of employees may have
on profit margins has been explicitly excluded from the BFOQ justification. The
policy considerations
concerning the employer's right to control its business
image are correspondingly quite weak.
A similar judicial yielding to the
purported need to protect an employer's managerial discretion can also be
discerned from an examination
of the English jurisprudence. For instance, the
Employment Appeals Tribunal in Schmidt placed reliance on the now
discredited Court of Appeal judgment of Peake v Automotive Products
Ltd158 to assert that because an employer was entitled to
'a large measure of discretion in the control of his establishment', judicial
interference
with the imposition of gender based dress codes was
ill-advised.159 However, as this element of the Peake judgment
had been rejected by the time of the Safeway decision,160 the
absence of any attempts by the Court of Appeal to scrutinise the Employment
Appeals Tribunal's endorsement of Peake is telling.161 In
fact, the purported right for an employer to control the image of its business
was explicitly recognised by the Court. Holding
that the employer in question
was at liberty to impose differing hair requirements for its staff, on the
supposedly 'sound commercial'
grounds that such appearance standards were what
the customers of the business required,162 the Court's rejection of
the discrimination claim appeared to be driven by the perceived imperatives of
customer preference. Such
policy concerns are unsound: there is no justification
provided for direct discrimination of this kind under the Sex Discrimination
Act,163 and the court's deference to the requirements of customer
preference was in flagrant disregard of the anti-discrimination
statute.164 Moreover, it is clear that in ascertaining whether or not
direct discrimination has occurred, the employer's underlying motives of
maintaining commercial viability should be of no relevance.165 The
Safeway reasoning is, in brief, flawed.
Floodgate Concerns
A profound objection to the potential judicial recognition of the illegality
of a gender based dress standard is based on the fear
that any judicial
proscription will inevitably open the floodgates to an unadulterated flow of
discrimination claims brought by employees
dissatisfied with their workplace
dress requirements.166 Such concerns were evident in Judge
Schroeder's contention in Jespersen that judicial recognition of the
claimant's sex stereotyping claim would come precariously close to holding every
grooming apparel
or appearance requirement that an individual finds personally
offensive to be a successful sex discrimination claim.167
These
concerns may at first sight have some superficial attraction. However,
assertions that recognition of the illegality of gender
based dress requirements
would inevitably result in the downfall of all employment dress codes are
unnecessarily alarmist. First
of all, it must be noted that judicial recognition
of a sex discrimination claim would not prevent the imposition of standards of
cleanliness and tidiness in the workplace, and a gender-neutral prohibition of
casual attire, such as T-shirts, jeans or trainers,
would not infringe any sex
discrimination legislation.168 Secondly, and on an entirely pragmatic
note, it is clear that compliance with dominant gender norms is unproblematic
for many individuals.
The eradication of compulsory gender based dress
requirements is therefore most unlikely to alter greatly the appearance of an
employer's
workforce, as the very nature of dominant norms entails that the
majority will seek to comply with them. The policy concerns over
the prospect of
a flood of discrimination claims are groundless.
VIII. NEW ZEALAND'S FUTURE JUDICIAL PATHWAY
The Approaches Open to the New Zealand Courts
It can be seen from the above analysis that the policy objections raised
against judicial recognition of the discriminatory effects
of gender based dress
concerns are ill-conceived, and should not impede the New Zealand courts from
recognising the illegality of
gender based appearance standards under our human
rights legislation. On the contrary, considerations of policy should in fact
propel
future judicial proscription of the use of such standards in the
workplace. The ever-increasing recognition of the need to ensure
transgendered
individuals have access to fundamental human rights, and the desirability of
combating oppressive gender ideologies
in the workforce, lend force to the
argument that such gender based dress codes should be judicially declared to be
prohibited under
New Zealand's human rights legislation. However, while there is
clear normative validity in the judicial recognition of dress code
discrimination claims, we are drawn to question how such a claim could feasibly
succeed under New Zealand's current legislative framework.
It is first
necessary to observe that the Employment Court's obiter contention in
Williams that a 'mutual [facial make-up] contractual
requirement'169 could not contravene New Zealand's human rights
legislation was misguided. A fundamental tenet of anti-discrimination law is
that
an employee's consent to a discriminatory term or condition of employment
does not serve to dilute its discriminatory effect.170 The Court's
emphasis of the purported mutuality of the appearance requirement was therefore
doubtful, and should not unduly influence
thinking on this issue.
While any
substantive examination of unjustified disadvantage grievances falls outside the
scope of this article, it must also be
noted that under New Zealand's
legislative framework the purported imposition of gender based dress standards,
pursuant to the introduction
of a new employment policy, could amount to a
unilateral variation of an employee's terms of employment171 and thus
provide grounds for an alternative disadvantage grievance to be brought under
the Employment Relations Act.172 Such an approach would
side-step the requirement for an employee to prove discrimination, and could be
an attractive possibility
for the claimant.
However, the fundamental question
for this article is whether, under New Zealand legislation, a gender based
appearance standard could
constitute unlawful discrimination 'by reason of' sex
under s 22 of the Human Rights Act 1993 (or s 104 of the Employment
Relations Act 2000). The essential question is, therefore, whether the
courts could find that a gendered dress or grooming requirement equates to a
'less
favourable term of employment' than that afforded to employees in 'the
same or substantially similar circumstances' as the
complainant.173
Some guidance can be gleaned from the overseas jurisprudence discussed above.
First of all, the issue could be resolved by following
the authoritative House
of Lords' approach in James, a judgment so assiduously avoided by the
Court of Appeal in Safeway. As the 'by reason of' causal test, provided
by the Human Rights Act, has been judicially interpreted in New Zealand
to accord with the House of Lords' 'but for' causal test,174 it can
readily be argued that a sex-differentiated appearance requirement (which denies
an employee a specific choice that is open
to the other sex)175
constitutes a 'less favourable term of employment' that has occurred 'by reason
of' the employee's sex. Under this approach a grooming
requirement that obliges
female employees to wear make-up to work, when men are not so obliged, would
contravene the legislation.
Similarly, a restriction placed on the ability of
men to wear makeup, or to wear dresses or skirts in the workplace, would
contravene
s 22 of the Human Rights Act. While such an approach is
attractive for its simplicity, it must be noted that it is not explicitly
premised upon the normative harms
of such requirements.
In the alternative,
guidance could be gleaned from the Ninth Circuit's acceptance in Jespersen
that any term of employment that requires an employee to conform to an
impermissible sex stereotype associated with his or her sex
amounts to a 'less
favourable' term of employment by reason of 'sex'. Such an approach does have
stronger normative justifications,
as it is explicitly premised upon the
undesirability of the perpetuation of gendered norms in the workplace.
Obviously, as argued
above, the more progressive dissent of Judge Pregerson in
Jespersen should be preferred. And, significantly, the principle of sex
stereotyping has already been recognised in the New Zealand judicial
system. In
obiter discussion in N v F176 the Equal Opportunities Tribunal
argued that discriminatory treatment driven by employer reliance on the notion
that females should
not have an 'assertive nature,' when this requirement was
not applied to men, could have breached New Zealand's human rights
legislation.177 The use of the sex-stereotyping principle to
proscribe gendered dress requirements could therefore be readily adopted by the
New
Zealand courts.
If the New Zealand courts were to be guided by the
dissent of Judge Pregerson in Jespersen, the issue does arise as to how
the 'impermissible sex stereotyping' prohibited by the judgment, could be
identified. Certainly, the
need for the court under Jespersen to make the
differentiation between permissible and impermissible gendered ideologies will
pose some difficulties. Nevertheless, many
scholars claim that a judicial
examination of the sociological implications of a gendered appearance standard
could be undertaken
to investigate its normative underpinnings.178
Under this approach, any compulsory requirements for females to adhere to
orthodox standards of grooming or dress would be seen as
invidious, and thus
proscribed. However, such an approach would initially appear to provide little
protection to male employees with
a female gender identity, as male dress norms
serve to communicate messages of power and dominance179 and arguably
might not be seen as intrinsically invidious. On the other hand, the origins of
the derision accorded to males who seek
to wear female attire derives from the
deeply held societal beliefs in the inferiority of women.180 The
argument can accordingly be made that any dress requirement that prohibits men
from adopting a form of appearance open to women
is inherently objectionable, as
it reinforces the subordinate nature of women in society.
This inquiry into
the validity of gendered stereotyping would not be required if discrimination on
the grounds of gender identity
was explicitly proscribed by the statute. While
the Crown Law Office has asserted 'it is unnecessary to amend the Human
Rights Act 1993 in order to ensure protection from discrimination on grounds
of gender identity'181 this pronouncement is somewhat optimistic. The
Crown Law opinion appeared to be simply based on the fact that Canadian and
United
Kingdom jurisprudence has established that transsexual individuals who
have undergone gender reassignment procedures are to be protected
from
discrimination on the grounds of sex.182 While these decisions may
well be of some assistance to the New Zealand courts, it is necessary to
emphasise that none are binding.
Moreover, it must be observed that the House of
Lords decision in Chief Constable of Yorkshire v A,183
that was relied upon in the Crown Law opinion, only widened the scope of the
term 'sex' to include gender-reassignment within its
parameters.184
This is quite distinct from providing protection from discrimination on the
wider grounds of gender identity185 and it is surprising that Crown
Law reached its conclusion so confidently. As recently recognised by the Human
Rights Commission,
there still remains a pressing need for a statutory amendment
to ensure that discrimination on the grounds of gender identity is
explicitly
proscribed by the statute,186 and it is by no means clear that an
individual's right to the expression of gender identity is currently
protected.
Thus, the discriminatory nature of dress codes may still have to
be recognised pursuant to the proposed approaches analysed above.
In order for
the courts to focus on the discriminatory nature of a specific appearance
standard, the James approach regarding the formulation of an appropriate
comparator in sex discrimination claims will need to be followed. This would
ensure that gender based dress requirements imposed on employees of the other
sex are excluded from the determination of what constitutes
a 'substantially
similar circumstance' under New Zealand's legislation, and such an approach
clearly accords with the broad and purposive
construction of human rights
legislation that is required under New Zealand law.187
It must,
however, be noted that the James analysis cannot be easily reconciled
with the Court of Appeal's recent decision in Air New Zealand v
McAlister.188 Here it was held by the Court that an age
based restriction on a pilot's ability to fly international flight paths could
be purportedly
compared to a hypothetical operational restriction imposed on
younger pilots in its determination of what amounted to a 'same or
substantially
similar circumstance' under s 104(1)(a).189 The discriminatory
impetus behind the age restriction therefore appeared to hold no relevance for
the Court190 and the implications of the decision are unfortunate.
Following McAlister, a gender based dress restriction imposed upon the
other sex could well be included within the scope of the comparison needed to
determine
if unlawful discrimination has occurred. Regrettably, it is apparent
that under McAlister the current abstracted method of comparative
analysis prevailing in international legal analysis would clearly be open for
the New
Zealand judiciary to adopt.
The Section 27 Exception
If, however, the discriminatory nature of gendered appearance standards was
to be recognised by the New Zealand courts, the issue
will arise as to whether
an employer is ever able to impose a gendered based dress requirement on its
employees. Under s 27(1) of
the Human Rights Act 'different treatment'
based on sex is permissible where, for reasons of 'authenticity,' being of a
particular sex is a 'genuine occupational
qualification'. While no legislative
or judicial guidance has been given as to the meaning of the two critical terms
within the section,
it is apparent that the term 'authenticity' greatly reduces
the potential scope of the provision. The term arguably refers to concepts
of
genuineness or validity,191 and it has been argued that this will
inform the nature of what could be considered to be a 'genuine occupational
qualification'.192 As noted above, the New Zealand courts are likely
to follow the American approach so as to exclude considerations of customer
preference
under this provision.193 The exception is likely to be
construed very narrowly.
The term 'different treatment' under s 27 is also
left undefined. It could, however, be assumed that a 'less favourable term of
employment'
would fall within the scope of this phrase. The question thus arises
as to the circumstances under which a gender based dress requirement
constituting 'different treatment' would be acceptable because, for reasons of
'authenticity', being of a particular sex is a 'general
occupational
qualification'. It is clear that in industries premised upon physical attributes
an individual's sex is likely to amount
to an authentic general occupational
qualification.194 Thus, in the modelling, sex, and dramatic
performance industries, an employer could require a female to comply with
appearance requirements
that reinforce dominant gender norms. Nonetheless, the
issue arises as to whether the contention of the Employment Court in
Williams, that a compulsory make-up requirement could be viably imposed
upon a female cosmetic sales assistant, would survive the rigorous s
27 test.
Under the Wilson framework, it is clear that an employer would be unable
to argue that customers prefer to buy cosmetics from female sales assistants.
Moreover, as the 'essence' of a retail sales job is to assist customers with
inquiries, and to operate a cash register, it is apparent
that the job could
just as easily be performed by a male employee. Accordingly, the Employment
Court's assertion does not appear
to accord with the spirit and wording of the s
27 exception.
IX. THE WAY FORWARD
The above examination shows that the international jurisprudence surrounding the imposition of gender based standards in the workplace lacks both legal and normative soundness, and that the New Zealand courts would be therefore be ill-advised to seek guidance from it. Clearly, considerations of policy should provide the underlying impetus for the judicial proscription of gendered dress codes in New Zealand, and the possible approaches proposed in this article provide a workable framework by which the illegality of such dress policies could be recognised under New Zealand's current legislation.
However, in light of the New Zealand Court of Appeal's questionable approach
towards the comparator issue in McAlister, there is a real danger that
that the broad method of comparative analysis evident in both the Jespersen
and Safeway decisions could be adopted by the New Zealand
courts.
Accordingly, as recently acknowledged by the Human Rights Commission,
the most appropriate means by which an individual's right to
express his or her
gender identity can be protected is through legislative intervention. The
international dress code jurisprudence
demonstrates that such a right will often
not be recognised under any general legislative proscriptions on sex
discrimination. It
is therefore to be hoped that Parliament will see fit to
follow the Human Rights Commission's recommendation, and amend the Human
Rights Act to ensure the statute specifically provides explicit protection
from discrimination on the grounds of gender identity.195 In the
light of the overseas jurisprudence, such a legislative amendment appears
necessary and should hopefully ensure that gendered
based dress codes are
rendered curious artifacts from the past.
* LLB(Hons), BA. Natasha is currently employed as a Judge's Clerk at the Court of Appeal. This paper was awarded the Canterbury Law Review prize for the best undergraduate Honours paper completed in 2008. The law discussed in this article is as at 31 January 2009.
Girls (2007) 22.
Auckland AP7-SW03, 12 May 2004, Baragwanath and Harrison JJ) 17.
...
(b) To offer or afford the applicant or the employee less favourable terms of employment, conditions of work, ... than are made available to applicants or employees of the same or substantially similar capabilities employed in the same or substantially similar circumstances on work of that description;
...
by reason of any of the prohibited grounds of discrimination.
(a) refuses or omits to offer or afford to that employee the same terms of employment, conditions of work ...as are made available for other employees of the same or substantially similar qualifications, experience, or skills employed in the same or substantially similar circumstances.
Note, while this requirement of the 'same terms of employment' appears less stringent than the 'less favourable' standard provided by s 22 of the Human Rights Act the Equal Opportunities Tribunal did note that the comparable term under s 15(1)(b) Human Rights Commission Act 1977 bore similarity to the standard of less favourable treatment: Proceedings Commissioner v Air New Zealand Ltd [1987] NZEOT 1; [1998] 7 NZAR 462, 470.
1981).
51, 55.
195 Report on the Inquiry into Transgendered Discrimination, above n 18, [9.50].
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/CanterLawRw/2009/1.html